Recent Posts

Hard Analysis

Finding analytical insights that help illuminate this confusing time in history is difficult. Doing such analysis is hard, and giving an analysis that is more than just rhetorical flourish wrapped around ideological presuppositions would be to provide a “hard analysis.” I just finished reading such a hard analysis in Chaos and Governance in the Modern World System by Giovanni Arrighi and Beverly J. Silver. The book is divided into four big chapters, and was cowritten with eight others, and presents a fascinating long-term view of hegemonic succession in the modern world.

To grossly simplify the book’s argument, there have been two previous historic transformations like the one that is now underway. The first was when the Dutch lost their control of the emerging transnational economy to the British, and the second was when the British Empire gave way to the U.S. Having denoted those as the main transformations, the authors delve into the specific processes by which it happened, the way the structure of business evolved through these transitions, the role of crisis and war in accelerating the deeper trends already observably underway. Remarkably, during the latter stages of losing hegemony, both Dutch and British finance capital enjoyed periods of expansion and apparent success, which corresponds closely to the reflation of U.S. power and financial control globally since the 1980s, well after the peak of U.S. world hegemony. The spasmodic thrashing of the dying beast visible now in Iraq and Afghanistan (who knows where else the small-minded theocrats and their corporate sponsors will attack before finally losing power) may serve the function that WWI played in undercutting British power, and the mid-18th century wars in Europe and North America played in dismantling Dutch power. One other interesting parallel in the big systemic process of change between the previous transitions and today’s is that in each case a financial crisis hit in the emerging power zone prior to the final demise of the existing hegemon. So a financial crisis in 1772 in London led to the unraveling of Dutch financial power in the following decade. The 1929 Crash in the U.S. led to a depression that with WWII finally destroyed British global financial power and paved the way for the U.S. More recently the 1997 East Asian financial collapse presages the rise of China and the whole east Asian region as the next dominant economic and political power in the world and the coming collapse of U.S. economic power.

The authors do not overstate their case and make clear in a series of five hypothetical propositions at the end of the book how the parallels to prior historic junctures help shed light on the momentous changes underway now, but also show how some crucial things are different now. In their second proposition, they note that unlike any previous case, there is now an unprecedented bifurcation of military and financial capabilities, which they think reduces the likelihood of war between the system’s most powerful units, though the same bifurcation is not capable of preventing a long period of systemic chaos. I would argue that with the emergence of an offensive U.S. war to control oil there will indeed be a long war, but as long as China, Russia, India and Brazil stay out of it, it will only serve to drain the resources of the declining hegemon and set the stage for a new global regime to emerge in its eventual wreckage. Clearly China is poised to assert itself in the coming years, but it’s not at all clear that it can lead to a new world system that resolves the problems left by the U.S.’s chaotic and self-serving endgame of plunder and destruction. (The unconscious reliance on systemic crisis as a prime motivator for radical change is one of the key points attacked by Roberto Unger in his What Should the Left Propose that I reviewed a week ago. While his proposals don’t ultimately satisfy me, I do appreciate that he boldly puts them into the public discussion. He concludes about his own prescription: “The advancement of alternatives like these would amount to world revolution. It would not deliver world revolution in the form we have been accustomed by the prejudices of nineteenth- and twentieth-century thought to associate with the idea of revolution: sudden, violent, and total change. The transformation would be gradual, piecemeal, and generally peaceful”¦ The most important sign that we will have succeeded would be that we would have diminished the dependence of change on crisis.”)

Arrighi and Silver point to the great proliferation in the number and variety of transnational business organizations and communities as unique to this period, and note how such a proliferation itself has accelerated the general disempowerment of states. That in turn has also produced the general hollowing out of social movements that depend on state intervention and state guarantees as their source of power, e.g. trade unions, etc. The authors make a general reference to the coming period as one in which there will be a changing spatial and ethnic configuration of the world’s labor force, which will also involve a much greater feminization of the same. The coming social conflicts will thus not be like the ones that characterized the 20th century or earlier.

And that loops me back to the ongoing question of “immaterial labor” new social subjects, and the search to understand what shape revolt might take now. After the Cambridge conference I felt the category of “immaterial labor” was really problematic and I’ve only grown more skeptical since then. In Cambridge I picked up a badly photocopied Aufheben #14 “Questions on Immaterial Labour”. It’s a tedious read itself, since it spends so much time beating up Negri and Hardt and Empire. I understand that N/H were responsible for popularizing the idea of “˜immaterial labor’ more than any other writers, but the detailed critique of their work leaves me yawning. Here’s some of their best writing summarizing part of their critique, which soon after this turns on a discussion of the confusion of subjectivity and objectivity in N/H and their ultimate religiosity!

“Negri and Hardt’s “˜new’ category of “˜immaterial’ labour, however, does not seem to be better than [the old category of mental labour]. Like “˜mental labour’ we have seen that immaterial labour includes side by side the call center worker and the top designer too. Using the wrong category, Negri and Hardt give themselves a hard time in trying to convince us why this category correctly encircles the potentially subversive “˜new subject: why the migrant, although he does manual work, is immaterial, and why the top designer, who is included in the category, is a revolutionary subject.”The problem of bad categories can be solved either by looking for more apprpropriate categories” or by making the bad category elastic enough to patch up all its shortcomings”¦ Negri and Hardt define”¦ immaterial labour”¦ as any possible human activity” either manual or mental, either done inside or outside the workplace” that produces ideas, communication or affections, either as product or a by-product. With this definition, immaterial labour can include anything. Indeed, what human activity is not an expenditure of thoughts, affects or an act of communication after all? Even the production of nothing can be seen as production of something: needs and desires, which are indeed human forms of affects and communications.

“The convenient elasticity of the category”¦ allows N/H to sneak into and out of the “˜subject’ of immaterial labour”¦ groups according to the current rating of sympathy scored in the liberal-leftist world. Thus black “˜communities’, tribes in the Pacific, housewives, students, Indian farmers fighting against the genetic industry, protesters involved in the anti-capitalist movement, workers in flexible jobs, economic migrants, the radical student and the academic like Negri are all in”¦. when anything”¦ can be considered as “˜production,’ we have found the Holy Grail of the theorist, the magic key for the Theory of Everything capable of accommodating everything in the end explaining nothing.”

On the other hand, there’s a link in it to John Holloway’s critique of Negri, which I found really well-written and concise compared to Aufheben’s 20 pages. Holloway has a different angle too. He is a long-time participant in the discussions around “autonomist Marxism” and his book Change The World Without Taking Power is a vital contribution, a stimulating recasting of the original idea of commodity fetishism. But in this article that originally appeared in Historical Materialism, he rebuts Negri for seeking to establish autonomist critique as a positive project. For Holloway it is impossible to meaningfully construct a revolutionary politics on anything else but a loud screaming NO, a basic negation of how our lives are reduced and stunted by life under capitalism. Holloway sharply takes apart the positive ontological project of Negri, insisting as he does in his book that “the world is not, there is no being, there is only doing, a doing torn asunder in such a manner that the done takes on a life of its own and appears to be”¦” I recommend reading Holloway’s argument, but here’s a quote I really liked from the end of it:

“We hate capitalism and fight against it, but that does not make us into the embodiment of good fighting against evil. On the contrary, we hate it not just because we adopt the common condition of the multitude, but because it tears us apart, because it penetrates us, because it turns us against ourselves, because it maims us. Communism is not the struggle of the Pure Subject, but the struggle of the maimed and schizophrenic.”

It’s too easy to get lost in arcane philosophy, reading one set of theoretical critiques against another. Often I find it quite interesting to a point and then suddenly I’m aghast at now much time I’ve spent on it, rather than doing my own work, seeking to understand the world I can observe and participate in. Of course these theories are important contributors to a larger framework of understanding and it’s just as loony to push them away as somehow separate and irrelevant. But it’s only one thread of a dense fabric I’m weaving these days. I’m also grappling with issues of science history and shifting paradigms, which I think dovetail into discussions of class composition and exodus from this mad moment in history in important ways”¦ more on that to come.

Capri

Back in San Francisco, here’s my last travel entry on Capri. We spent Monday at Capri and were amazed at its beauty and (unlike anywhere else around here) its pedestrian-friendliness. Here’s the view from the dock as you disembark at Capri.

And here’s a map of the Bay of Naples so you can see where the island is, about 40 minutes south-southwest of the city.

We immediately set out to the northeast corner of the island where the Roman emperor Tiberius held court for 10 years from 26-36 AD in what was then a palace dominating the island and the entire empire. Now it’s another beautiful ruin. We had a picnic in the ruins again and enjoyed peering over the cliff that Tiberius used to throw his enemies.

Continue reading Capri

What Should the Left Propose?

While in Italy I read a new book from Brazilian political theorist Roberto Mangabeira Unger called What Should the Left Propose? I don’t tend to identify with the label “left” these days (and certainly not “right”!) but I’m still interested in what different thinkers are coming up with as they try to grapple with this odd moment in history. So many friends and acquaintances are groping for something effective, something that will make a difference, and yet I can’t think of any current initiatives that overcome the dead-ends with which we are already all too familiar.

Unger, who I first saw cited by David Harvey in his stimulating Spaces of Hope, has been an advisor to the Brazilian Workers Party of Lula, currently in power, but I don’t know what the nature of his current relationship is. In this book he’s trying to offer an approach that can be adopted by the left in the global south and north, and in countries that are more or less democratic. His rhetoric falls rather short for me, as he tends to offer generalities about the kinds of social dynamics he wants to encourage, and the ways that current politics stunts us as individuals and as a society. At certain moments his ideas start to resonate, as when he says “political parties and social movements are insufficient instruments in this prophetic work,” indicating an idea that I too hold, that the political forms we’ve received are defunct and we must invent new ones. But later in the book he comes back around to his leftist roots and contradicts this insight by proposing that “To be fertile for the cause of democracy and for the program of the Left, high-temperature politics must be institutionalized rather than anti-institutional or extra-institutional. To this end, the political arrangements must favor whatever electoral regimes encourage the development of strong political parties, with well-defined programmatic profiles.”

To nurture his idea of “high-temperature politics” he makes a number of matter-of-fact proposals that in the U.S. context sound hopelessly naïve, e.g., the proposal that all private money should be removed from politics, and that all parties and movements have open and fair access to mass communications. I agree that such a reform would drastically bolster democratic tendencies within the U.S. body politic, but what kind of social power would be able to extract such an enormous leveling of the political field? It’s a bit of a Catch-22 proposal, to say the least, though he does at one point acknowledge that his program “addresses a constituency that does not yet exist: a working-class majority that is able to transcend its commitments to racial and religious divisions.”

I like some of what he says about democracy: “Democracy is about the permanent creation of the new.” He claims the kinds of reforms he is pushing would “turn democratic politics into a machine for the permanent invention of the future.” He makes a lot of lists and one of them describes five parts that would constitute a “high-energy democracy”” the fifth would combine elements of representative democracy with direct democracy (he thinks that in governments with “˜checks and balances’ any branch should be able to dissolve an impasse by calling an instant election that would allow citizens to vote directly either in plebiscites or for new representatives). “The goal is not only to melt structure without disorganizing politics; it is also to render commonplace in everyday life the experience of effective agency.” (p. 81)

At some moments he captures something important about what we’re trying to achieve, philosophically and psychologically. A fair amount of the book is spent debunking the common conceptions that underly European social democracy, or North Atlantic liberalism for that matter. He insists that the limited thinking that focuses on redistribution and amelioration of the worst oppressions is precisely wrong. He wants a Left politics that speaks to the broad population and incites their deep yearning to live big lives, to experience agency, to gain independence and at the same time to thrive in cooperative and competitive relationships.

“Self-construction depends on connection, and connection threatens to entangle us in toils of subjugation and to rob us of the very distinction that we can only develop thanks to it. There is a conflict between the enabling conditions of self-affirmation. To diminish that conflict is to become freer and greater, not by living apart but by living together while deepening the experience of self-possession.” (p. 102)

“No anxiety must be more central to democracy, and therefore to social democracy, than the fear that progress toward greater prosperity and equality may be unaccompanied by an advance in the capabilities and in the self-affirmation of ordinary humanity.” (p. 95)

The part of Unger’s work that I find most unpalatable (but I bet a lot of my less doctrinaire friends would find refreshing and creative) is his unabashed enthusiasm for market mechanisms. He is intelligently critical of the current ideological uses made of the idea of “free markets” but he rejects an anti-market position altogether.

“Leftists should not be the ones who seek to suppress the market, or even merely to regulate it or to moderate its inequalities by retrospective compensatory redistribution. They should be the people who propose to reinvent and to democratize the market by extending the range of its legal and institutional forms. They should turn the freedom to combine factors of production into a larger freedom to experiment with the arrangements that define the institutional setting of production and exchange.”

I really can’t figure out what this means if it isn’t a program that parallels the latest developments in capitalism. His concomitant proposals for lifelong education confirm that he is describing a program in which the logic of capital is encouraged to penetrate even further into the imaginations of everyone. Thinking in terms of markets, equity, capital and growth, while educating the broad population to be highly flexible and adaptable is almost exactly the cutting edge of capitalism these days. How odd that Unger’s program is so in tune with what we might call “googlism”: “Not only must the gateway to the existing advanced sectors be opened more widely but the methods of work and invention that flourish within these advanced sectors must be transplanted to many other parts of the economy and society.”

Of course his massive program of socially supported free education is a major investment; his primary practical suggestion for funding the huge reforms he favors is to impose a Value-Added Tax on consumption, which he acknowledges would be highly regressive at first. But he thinks if the state and new venture capitalist-like social entities that it helps fund with the greatly enlarged tax revenues produce tangible reforms in opportunity and education that people will come to support the short-term unfairness for the long-term gains.

This whole approach reminds me a bit of one of my first political experiences, the Tom Hayden campaign for U.S. Senate from California in 1976. At that time Hayden was espousing a doctrine he called “Economic Democracy” which by most accounts was a euphemism for socialism. But I found it quite inspiring when I was 19 years old. It felt like a way of breaking with the stodgy dogmatism of the left then. It probably still is. But breaking with the dead-end left can’t be achieved by embracing the real domination of capital, the complete subsumption of individual and social life under the logic of buying and selling. We have already lived through a radical expansion of that logic during this three-decade erosion of social rights, standards of living, and globalization.

I don’t think Unger is in any way in favor of reproducing and extending the society that is imposing itself on the planet today. And his book is an admirable attempt to describe some principles and even make practical proposals for radical reforms that would move the Left, or those of us who want humans to flourish in their full humanity, to a new self-conception. More importantly, Unger wants to describe social goals that might actually inspire most people to embrace a life of innovation and experimentation, trusting change and trusting each other, reaching new levels of self-actualization within a society based on high levels of social solidarity, flexibility and tolerance. That all sounds great! I just think the pernicious logic of the market, no matter how democratized, will keep pushing people into fetishized and alienated lives, a world where “Things are in the Saddle and Ride Mankind” as Ralph Waldo Emerson put it over 150 years ago.